Insanity as a Defense [excerpt]
There are several reasons why the
plea of insanity should not be permitted to save a murderer from
his fate, and these reasons are closely allied with those ordinarily
advanced in justification of punishment. In the first place, the
example afforded by this maudlin leniency is most pernicious. Of
the convicted murderers, few come to their deserved end. Insanity,
political influence, sentimentality, are the pleas and means of
commuting the death sentence into life imprisonment; and the person
who is tempted to homicide is not deterred by the thought that there
will be but one result to his deed—that his life must atone for
the life he is about to take. With the true instinct of the gambler,
he weighs the chances and finds the odds in his favor. His insanity
makes him all the more reckless, and with one final [123][124]
psychologic impulse the deed is done, and the pitiful brute becomes
a murderer. How far example has moved him to the commission of the
crime would be hard to say; how far the hope of immunity from extreme
punishment has urged him on would be difficult to measure. Criminologists
tell us that example is a factor, however, and legists tell us that
certainty of punishment is a deterrent. If, then, capital punishment
is a valuable and effective part of our penal code, it is illogical
to discriminate. One murderer is as deserving of death as another,
and the value of the punishment is weakened by saving the life of
the least worthy. Had not public opinion demanded the deaths of
Probst, Guiteau, Holmes, and Czolgosz, the defense could easily
have found experts to declare these men insane. You can prove anything
by an expert: he is the only witness whom the law permits to testify
as to his opinion, and the opinions of men may honestly differ upon
the same state of facts. What would have been the effect upon other
defectives had these men been permitted to escape death?
|