Anarchism and the Law
T people of the United States have shown
a great reluctance to deal severely with anarchism. The tradition
that America is an asylum for the oppressed, and the belief that
perfect freedom of political discussion is essential to liberty,
have great vitality. European nations have often reproached us for
failing to distinguish between a liberty of utterance that is expedient,
and a criminal raving that is known to be closely associated with
conspiracy and assassination. More than once our relations with
Great Britain have been strained by our toleration of dynamiters.
Italy, if not formulating a legal complaint, is undoubtedly cherishing
a moral grievance against us for our easy-going indifference to
the Paterson gang that plotted and have gloried in the murder of
a generous and high-minded king. Even when our own domestic peace
has been threatened we have still held strongly to the policy of
letting anarchism alone until overt violence could be proven. The
hanging of the Haymarket anarchists at Chicago was strongly disapproved
by a large and influential class of theorists, and by not a few
minds of a more practical turn. Lawyers especially have held that
Judge Gary’s rulings strained the fundamental principles of constitutional
law. “So [2187][2188]
long as the anarchist only talks, and until he does something,
he cannot be molested.” This has been our creed.
Whether the assassination of President
McKinley by an avowed anarchist, following so closely upon the taking
off of Carnot, the Empress Elizabeth and King Humbert, will bring
the American people and their legislative bodies to a severer view
it is not easy to predict; but there are indications, in the attitude
of the press, and in the utterances of public men, that give some
hope of broader and more courageous thinking. The first wave of
indignation will expend itself in threats of “extermination,” and
similar violent language, and that is on all accounts to be desired.
We are already quite prone enough in this country to substitute
irregular punishments for due process of law. What the situation
calls for is a sober, thoughtful reconsideration of the whole problem
of the relation of anarchism to a republican government, an exhaustive
discussion of all its possibilities by clear-headed leaders of public
opinion, and the adoption of a policy that shall be at once lawful,
rigorous, prompt and efficient.
The first step in such a policy is
to make clear to the people the difference, which is not generally
recognized even by the better newspapers, between a creed of peaceful
anarchism and the propaganda of criminal anarchism. There are men
against whom no breath of reproach has ever been uttered who believe
as an article of philosophy that all government of man by man is
morally wrong. The Society of Friends, while not going quite to
this length, holds doctrines that very closely approach the denial
of the rightfulness of human government. Count Tolstoi, we suppose,
while not calling himself an anarchist, is almost or quite an anarchist
in philosophical conviction. But philosophical anarchism, when combined
with a literal interpretation of the injunction to “resist not evil,”
is harmless to the community. There can be no possible objection
to allowing men to argue that all employment of force in the relations
of man to man is morally indefensible; and, if they derive from
this principle the conclusion that governments, making use of guns
and bayonets and policemen’s clubs are wrong, they can harm nobody
so long as they also teach that forcible resistance to government
likewise is wrong.
Absolutely different is the anarchism
that is essentially criminal, and that often develops into actual
crime. When one-half of the creed of philosophical anarchism—that,
namely, which denies the rightfulness of government—is adopted by
fanatics, neurotics, and instinctive criminals, while the other
half—namely, the gospel of non-resistance—is ignored or discarded,
the result is an exceedingly dangerous product which, by its very
nature, is bound to assume a criminal character, and, unless watched
and restrained by the community, to grow into murder and revolution.
The second step in a sound policy
toward anarchism must be a clear recognition that certain forms
of insanity cannot be dealt with on the easy-going plan of laisser
faire. Criminal anarchism has received much aid and comfort
from well meaning men, some of a scientific and some of a sentimental
turn, who have protested that the anarchist who counsels violence
is prima facie an unbalanced and irresponsible person. On
this whole subject of a right relation of the law to irresponsible
characters there is endless confusion in the public mind. Irresponsibility
is a sufficient reason for withholding those punishments which imply
a judgment of guilt, and which contain an element of vengeance,
or retribution. It is no reason whatever for allowing the irresponsible
person, or faction, to go at large, to the deadly peril of useful
and law-abiding men, and a continuing menace to the social order.
Let it then be granted that anarchists of the blood-thirsty sort
are irresponsible creatures, if science so declares. A way must
be found within the forms of law to prevent them from putting their
creed of violence into practice.
And this brings us to the third step
which must be taken in any rational policy of dealing with criminal
anarchism. We have had quite enough of the nonsense of waiting until
the criminal anarchist murders somebody before taking him in hand.
Too many valuable lives have been sacrificed already, and our constitutional
liberty has been subjected to an altogether unnecessary peril. Criminal
insanity is a medico-legal [2188][2189]
phenomenon that has long been recognized in the statutes and by
the decisions of the courts of all civilized countries. The criminally
insane may be and are deprived of liberty upon proof of criminal
conduct, altho their acts have proceeded from irresponsible impulses,
or from delusion. It is for the law-making power to say what acts
shall be construed as criminal, and what evidence shall be deemed
sufficient to establish the fact of criminal insanity. Is it necessary,
then, to wait until the criminal anarchist has shot some one, or
thrown a bomb, before placing him safely behind the bars? We think
that it is time to recognize and to define by law as criminal all
advocacy of assassination as a political method, all participation
in meetings in which violence is approved, and all expressions of
satisfaction in deeds of violence already committed. Proof of such
expressions, or advocacy, or participation, in connection with a
plea of irresponsibility by the defense, should then be declared
sufficient evidence of criminal insanity, and restraint in a safe
place of detention should be provided for those found guilty.
In the policy here suggested there
would be no violation of any rational principle of liberty. It is
a policy demanded by common sense to meet a serious and growing
evil. The alternative is a frequent recurrence of assassination.
Let us, then, have a legal recognition
of the criminality of murderous anarchism, and a law providing restraint
for life for all who preach or glory in assassination, whether they
plead insanity or not.
|