Observations [excerpt]
Henry Addis would correct the impression,
which is strangely prevalent, that there are two kinds of Anarchists—the
Philosophical and the Red. Mr. Addis tells us that all Anarchists
are philosophical, but some are more so than others. The difference
is in degree, not in kind. A man completely possessed by the philosophy
will not commit deeds of violence; when one professing to be an
Anarchist commits such a deed, we must attribute it to the old archic
Adam that is still in him—the survival from former times of belief
in force and oppression. The reason men do wrong is that they are
not genuinely converted to Anarchistic principles. All which sounds
plausible enough, but is fallacious. The line drawn by Livesey is
no imaginary thing; a professed Anarchist either believes in assassination
or he does not, and his belief on that subject naturally puts him
on the other side of the line from those who take the opposite view.
When people differ about methods, there is all the difference in
the world between them; other differences are minor. As to Anarchists,
I should imagine that the item of murder, concerning which they
are not agreed (some being so squeamish as to deprecate assassination),
would be important enough to be called divisive. Even the temperance
people are divided, some being for force and some not. Carrie Nation,
I understand, has not the approval of all who are on the sober list.
In a very particular sense the propagandists by deed belong to the
same class as the Kansas joint-smasher, and their claim to affiliation
with the Philosophicals is defective. They are Carrienationalists.
[omit]
It is reported by persons who witnessed
the execution that as the headgear of the electrical apparatus was
adjusted, the forepart covering his face, the voice of Czolgosz
was heard saying something construed to be: “I am sorry I did not
see father.” The regret was rather a strange one to be expressed
under the circumstances, but the press accepted it as the only indication
of natural feeling the murderer had shown. However, it is to be
suspected that the father had in mind by the wretch was not his
earthly parent but his spiritual father, the Polish priest who visited
him in his cell, and who, for some reason, was not present at the
time. The man whom Czolgosz slew had passed away without ghostly
counsel. There may have been a grim determination on the part of
the prison officials that the murderer should have no advantage
over his victim at the start on the long journey. One born and reared
a Catholic would in the presence of death be more likely to think
of his priest than of his family, and would inevitably refer to
him as “the father.”
These last inarticulate words should
be understood in the light of probability. When Sir John Falstaff
made what Mrs. Quickly declared to be “a finer end, and went away,
an it had been any christom child,” the lady noted that he “babbled
of green fields.” From this it has been thought that Falstaff’s
mind was occupied with his childhood’s happy home; but the Higher
Criticism as applied to Shakspere reaches the conclusion that Sir
John, knowing he was a goner, essayed to repeat something that would
be quoted to show he had died as a Christian should. “Nearer, my
God, to Thee,” was not then available, so he fell upon something
he had learned from the psalter: “He maketh me to lie down in green
pastures; he leadeth me beside the still waters.” The “green fields”
Falstaff babbled of were the pastures of the prayer book. The father
that Czolgosz babbled about was the priest.
——————————
It is sometimes a matter of luck
whether what a person has to say gives him immortality or six months
in jail. When Patrick Henry, arising to make a few remarks for the
benefit of the king of England, said that “Cæsar had his Brutus,
Charles I. his Cromwell, and George III.—might profit by their example,”
he owed it to his environment that he was not hanged. This will
be plainly seen if we imagine some speaker on or about the first
of last September declaiming as follows: “Lincoln had his Booth,
Garfield his Guiteau, and William McKinley—should take warning from
their fate.” That speaker would now be doing time. This shows how
the merit of an observation is modified by circumstances.
The best rule when talking for the
good of those in high places is to avoid allusion to the misfortunes
of their predecessors. Nobody believes in your warnings, and as
a prophet you take no stock in your own predictions, but if anything
happens your remarks will be recalled to your disadvantage. Two
years ago a Californian named Morrison I. Swift wrote a book abusing
McKinley. Probably the President never saw the work, and, if he
had seen it, would have found it uninteresting. There is nothing
to show that anybody was benefited by the work except the author,
whose mind it relieved, or that any person regarded its admonitions
as worth heeding; nevertheless, following the death of the President,
Mr. Swift was arrested for “slandering the memory of William McKinley.”
The case raises the question whether
the memory of a distinguished person can be slandered in advance,
or at least whether we can be certain that any living person is
going to leave a memory; and it complicates the situation a good
deal. When Mr. Swift wrote his book, Mr. McKinley belonged to the
present and did not have to be recalled, and he had not yet achieved
a memory. Can that be slandered which does not exist? Of course
it is hard to distinguish in words between the man himself and his
memory, but undoubtedly there is a difference. You cannot perpetuate
a man as you can his memory; he does not grow brighter as the eons
roll on. On the other hand, his memory can not bring an action for
slander, as can the man himself: it is not hurt in its business
by being talked about. If you can slander a man’s memory before
the close of the career that is going to determine what sort of
a memory he shall leave behind him, then you can desecrate his grave
before it is dug; and that, I fancy, is absurd.
But admitting that a man’s memory
can be slandered either before or after he has one, shall it be
criminal for a citizen to attack the memory of a President, and
yet guiltless for a President to attack the memory of a citizen?
That is to say, for example, is Mr. Swift, for his assault on President
McKinley’s memory, more deserving of punishment that [sic] is President
Roosevelt for libeling the memory of Thomas Paine? I admit a trifling
difference in the circumstances, for it is undeniable that while
the offense against McKinley was committed after he was President
but before he had a memory, on the other hand Roosevelt perpetrated
the outrage against Paine after Paine had a memory but before Roosevelt
was President; but I believe Mr. H. L. Green or any other lawyer
will agree with me that this distinction cannot hold good in law.
Hence I repeat the question, Is Swift more guilty than Roosevelt?
and I pause for a reply.
|