Anarchy: The Status of Anarchism To-Day in Europe
and the United States
HE who studies the theory of anarchy may find it strange and paradoxical,
but will also allow it to be worthy of discussion and consideration.
There are even some very striking truths embodied in this theory.
One of these is, for instance, that it is not necessary to surrender
one’s own initiative into the hands of other individuals, called
magistrates, ministers, and so forth, since they are anything but
infallible, and often more apt to do harm than good. Even if men
of infinite knowledge and integrity existed, by the mere fact that
they belonged to the government their power for good would be paralyzed,
from the necessity urging men at the head of affairs to settle matters
in which they are incompetent.
Government, says Kropotkin, has always
been the violent domination of the few over the masses, a machine
for the maintenance of the privileges of those who by force, cunning,
or inheritance have captured all the means of production. It is
very true, also, that the protection of governments is in nearly
all cases nil; that one does not desist from murder for fear
of the police; that there are thousands of people who live far away
from the police. Gambling debts are not guaranteed by the law, and
yet are paid. But the anarchists lay themselves open to contradiction
when they advise authors to become the printers and publishers of
their own books, and, worse still, propose to substitute for the
demolished machinery of government the will of the masses, of the
populace. They would leave every one free to share impartially in
the necessities of life by “taking from the heap,” like wild animals,
but they do not reflect that, like beasts, once the booty became
insufficient men would prey upon one another. Nor do these theorists
see that if a government often does harm, a collectivity can do
much more harm, simply because it is a much larger body. But all
of this is debatable at least. The worst of it is that a party among
the anarchists believe the supreme remedy for their ills to be the
destruction of property and proprietors, and even of the government.
By this means they hope to bring about the radical changes they
wish for at one sweep. But they forget that nothing in nature and
nothing in human society is accomplished permanently by improvisation
or by a catastrophe; that in order to be finally accepted changes
must be slow and imperceptible, and that success gained by crime
only provokes counteraction from an opposite source. There is thus
some truth in the anarchist idea, especially in the criticism of
government and in the spur given to individual initiative, but the
means suggested for carrying out the improvements are absurd. And
when one comes to examine personally, not the theorists of anarchy,
but its soldiers—not to say its executioners—one is confronted by
a number of the wildest anomalies. In order to have reached this
militant stage a tremendous degeneration must have taken place,
not merely of the intelligence, but also of the moral sense. It
is not enough to be an excessive innovator—which might seem an advantage,
but yet is always anomalous—but the persuasion must have been reached
that, as in the beginning of the race, crime and action are the
same thing, that human life is not a sacred thing, nor murder the
greatest of crimes.
There is, in fact, a large number
of madmen and criminals among the anarchists. We have regular criminals,
like Pini and Ravachol. Even Jean Grave, who was no criminal, wrote:
“Appropriation by force must be the anarchists’ prelude to the wholesale
insurrection which they will sooner or later enact.” Commonvale
[sic] wrote: “Theft is the recovery by violence from the
rich of that which the rich have taken by violence [165][166]
from the poor.” I have myself found typical criminal characteristics
in thirty-four out of one hundred Italian anarchists, and in forty
per cent. among fifty North American anarchists. Further proofs
of their criminal proclivities are their use of thieves’ jargon,
their songs peculiar to jailbirds, and their addiction to tattooing.
We also have a number of epileptics among them, and I have even
found some of these whose complaint was accompanied by a fancy for
politics. I knew a varnisher who told me in prison, where he had
been confined for vagrancy: “If social reforms come into my mind,
and I speak to my comrades about them, I seem to become dazed and
blind, and I fall down.” Felica, who had attempted several assassinations
and taken part in strikes, was an epileptic, and so was, as I have
shown elsewhere, Caserio, and likewise Santiago Salvador, who was
a Carlist in his youth and afterwards an anarchist. “I am an anarchist,”
said he, “not only by conviction, but by instinct. When I committed
the crime at the Liceo, I did it from an impulse I could not resist.”
Gori, an anarchist leader, stated of his adherents: “Among the anarchists
there are some who declare that if a certain impulse arises in them
it must be satisfied. Thus, when they feel the need of killing a
man, they imagine the thing is permissible, and that they must do
it.” Then we have insane anarchists like Monei, who was implicated
in a dynamite outrage in London, and subsequently adjudged mad by
two New York doctors. To this class belong especially the half-witted
people I call mattoids, since, though they have a rational manner
of conducting themselves under ordinary circumstances, in writing
and speaking they are demented. They believe themselves persecuted,
and, when carried away by a paroxysm of their malady, or stung by
poverty or ill-treatment, end by committing a crime. Such was Luccheni.
“At first I was horrified at the idea of murder,” he confessed;
“but soon I found that a real inspiration had seized upon me. I
felt inspired for a fortnight. I could not eat, and could think
of nothing but the assassination, but as soon as it was done sleep
and appetite came back to me.” Büchner cites the case of a mattoid
who thought himself persecuted, and who founded a society for persons
ill-used by the courts of law, sending a prospectus of the society
to the king.
Some anarchists are victims to alcoholism.
I studied a strange specimen of this sort for a long time, who declared
himself endowed with a mission to kill kings. Being arrested, he
denied his alleged mission altogether, even asserting that he was
a fervent monarchist. But after drinking a litre [quart]
of wine, which his relatives brought him, he suddenly became a wild
anarchist who wanted to kill the king, and even the prison guards.
The next day he denied it all again. It was then that I resolved
to experiment upon him with alcohol. I saw how this man, who after
consuming forty grammes [616 grains] was still an average,
commonplace individual, and even a monarchist, upon taking ninety
grammes [1,389 grains] became furiously anarchistic against
the prison guards; at the same time his eyes distended. It must
be confessed, however, that in childhood he had suffered from meningitis.
Other anarchists are indirect suicides, desperate people glad to
find the opportunity of being put to death for the murder of a king
or a president. Such an one was Henry, who forbade his lawyer to
mention the extenuating circumstance of his father’s insanity, and
who said to the court that the lawyer’s part was to defend him and
that his own part was to die. Frattini, who threw a bomb in the
Piazza Colonna, at Rome, with the object of protesting against the
existing order of things, had previously written: “I have no fear
for my liberty, nor for my life—in fact, to get rid of it would
be the greatest blessing to me.” Passanante declared that he committed
his act of assassination with the certainty of being killed; his
life had become a burden to him owing to the bad treatment he had
been subjected to. The same statement was made by Oliva and Nobili.
But the majority—and this is the thing
which renders them less hateful and less repulsive—are criminals
by temperament. Some of these even have fine faces, like Bakunin
and Sassulich; and among the criminal anarchists of America, Pearson,
Spies, Lingg, Fisher, Schwabe, Niebe, and Schaubel had ample foreheads,
clustering hair and beard, soft eyes, and altogether gentle mien.
Most of this category are very young. Otero was nineteen, Solovieff
and Staps eighteen, Booth twenty-seven. They never have accomplices.
The police endeavored to find some in the cases of Oliva, of Sand,
of Passanante, of Moncusi, of [166][167]
Bresci, and of Czolgosz, but they did not succeed. It is a fact
that the alleged Chicago conspiracy, which cost so many anarchists
their lives, was an invention of the police.
One of the most striking traits of
the anarchists is their love of innovation, the majority of men
being conservative. Thus Spies said, when he was about to be executed,
that he had finally concluded humanity was the slave of custom and
regarded habit as its nurse. These people are carried away by new
ideas for no other reason than their novelty. And to this is added
an exaggerated altruism, an intense desire to undergo suffering.
“It is sweet to suffer,” one of the Besi said to Dostoiewski. Like
religious fanatics, they like suffering for its own sake. Thus a
female nihilist of St. Petersburg, who was near death’s door from
a long siege of consumption and the hardships of prison life, improvised
a beautiful poem:
“My offence is grave and terrible.
Clad in coarse garments I wended my way barefoot to the place where
our brothers lay moaning, there where no respite is from poverty
and toil. But what purpose shall words serve? However guilty I may
be, yet do I judge you. You are powerless against me, for I have
faith—which in you is lacking—faith in the triumph of an idea! You
may imprison me for life, but my malady will abridge my woes. I
shall die with my heart full of that great love, and the very jailers,
throwing down their dungeon keys, will burst into tears at my bedside.”
Their faith, and the notion of being
useful to humanity makes them bold in the face of sacrifice, and
precludes the repentance which is frequent after crimes due to temperament.
Several anarchists, too, have led blameless lives. Spies was so
charitable that out of a small weekly salary he gave part to a sick
friend. His comrades said that if the revolution succeeded he would
have to be locked up, lest he should injure the revolution by his
sentimentality. Louise Michel was called “the red angel of the sick”
in Scotland. Of this sort was also Caserio, whom I studied very
particularly, who had always been honest, and who killed Carnot
to avenge the sufferings of his kin and the indignities heaped upon
the humble by their superiors. It is true that this hypersensitiveness,
this extravagant altruism, is partly ascribable to hereditary morbidness.
Nobiling, Booth, and Alibaud were the sons of suicides. The Padlewskis
had a father, a brother, and a grandfather who had been involved
in a revolt. The whole Pearson family had participated in revolutionary
movements for a century. Booth’s father styled himself Junius Brutus.
His father and Staps’s were religious maniacs. Fielden’s father
was one of the foremost labor agitators in England. But persons
of this class are also under the spell of a kind of monomania, of
an absolute obsession by a single idea, which produces hypersensitiveness
and makes them excessively susceptible to the influence of others
who second their idea, to the exclusion of all contrary arguments.
Czolgosz was one of these. He had inherited morbid tendencies. His
father had been concerned in the murder, or lynching, of a contractor
who ill-treated his workmen. Czolgosz, in the rare instances in
which he departed from silence, confessed to having been incited
to crime by the speeches of Emma Goldmann against the United States
form of government. It seems probable that this is the truth. Emma
Goldmann appears to me as the true type of the American anarchist.
Of foreign extraction, and descended from a doubly unfortunate race,
resident in American [sic] for ten years, after changing
among several lovers as fanatical as herself (she thought Most ultra-conservative),
she preached that the day was dawning when women would cook dynamite
instead of coffee. Her speeches may well have carried away a man
hereditarily predisposed, a fanatic at the same time, and given
to dark views on the misfortunes of his country. The Goldmann woman
intoxicated herself with words and declamation, but Czolgosz went
so far as actual murder, even considering it meritorious. However,
after the anarchist influences had ceased to reach him for some
time, and after seeing the horror of the whole American people at
his deed, he appeared slightly repentant. Perhaps, if he had lived,
he might, like Luccheni, Rochefort, and Drumont, have changed from
the spirit of revolt to the opposite extreme of conservatism, with
the same fanatical blindness. Like all criminals by temperament,
Czolgosz had no accomplices. True, the police of America, like that
of Europe, at once scented a number of accomplices; but the formless
nature of anarchism, in fact, opposes the idea of a regular conspiracy.
But the difference [167][168] was that
in the United States the truth was soon recognized, whereas in Europe
the supposed accomplices of Caserio and Luccheni and Bresci are
still in prison. Czolgosz was a foreigner—a Pole—an alien, as are
most of the anarchists in the United States—Italians, Russians,
Spaniards, Poles. In North America, indeed, anarchy exists only
through importation, and its adherents are distributed by nationality
over five or six districts.
There is reason, of course, for the
prevalence of anarchy, and for its flourishing condition, in countries
where there are no means of obtaining justice, and where the government
is so bad that anything seems preferable to submission to it, and
where, too, nominally at least, it is vested in one man. So that
in Russia anarchy is comprehensible, and in Italy too, and in Spain,
in which countries it goes hand-in-hand with brigandage and the
camorra, a very vile system of justice, something like lynch
law on a grand scale. Here, where enormous and irreparable social
grievances are to be met with, one understands the existence of
anarchy. But it is not easily explained in a country like America,
where there is real liberty, and where a bad government falls, or
always has a formidable opposition which brings about its defeat
when it seems on the verge of triumph. The excessive protectionism
and the imperialistic inclinations of the McKinley government had
already found strong opposition; there was hence no necessity for
a fanatic to kill a man who was not an omnipotent ruler, and whose
successor might come from a party with principles exactly the reverse
of his.
But then, it will be asked, how is
it that other American Presidents have been slain, irrespective
of the last? Here it must be taken into consideration that the other
assassins were not anarchists, but that Guiteau was a maniac and
Booth a fanactic [sic]—both under the sway of party opinions.
Now, apart from the fact that there are lunatics in all countries,
history supplies us with a foundation for these political crimes
which redounds entirely to the credit of America. In every country
of the world where there has been great liberty, it has been observed
that the assassination of the heads of parties has been easiest.
The most glorious days of Venice and Florence and Athens have been
conspicuous for the murder of chiefs of the government. At first
sight this seems the veriest paradox, because we have said that
this was just what happened under the worst governments. Although,
however, the causes are contrary, the effects are alike: in the
case of a bad government it is the hope of killing in one man the
evil condition of a country under his authority. Here, it must be
said, if attempts are numerous success is rare, owing to the employment
of police and soldiery who surround an autocrat, and the cowardice
engendered by tyranny. In very free countries the cause is quite
different. There it is the vehemence of the parties, which, buffeting
one another like the waves of the sea, break into extremes of fanaticism,
and thence into political crime. In America there have always been
two or more parties violently at odds. In the first half of the
nineteenth century there were the Slave party and the anti-Slave
party; in the fifties, the Republicans and the Democrats; in the
seventies the Prohibition party sprang up, and after the Populists
came the gold Democrats. The furious struggles of so many parties
often end in a victory for what is good and right, but in the interval
they influence the passionate and the violent and the half-witted,
and drive them to political assassination. During the most flourishing
period of Venetian liberty out of fifty doges nine were exiled,
ten deprived of their eyesight or killed, and five forced to abdicate.
At the time when liberty was at its height in Florence and Athens,
the hostile parties in turn banished their adversaries, or took
away their vote. So that while anarchist crime in Europe proves
the desperation of peoples oppressed by despotic tyranny, political
murder in America, especially that of the Presidents—that is of
frequent recurrence—merely demonstrates the immediate fanaticism
of parties to whom liberty allows the fullest scope. Thus, Lincoln
and Garfield, like McKinley, are holy victims sacrificed on the
altar of liberty.
|