The Treatment of Anarchism
I.
THERE was no text-book on criminal law used in the Columbia Law
School when I was a student. The treatment was confined to a brief
and non-compulsory course of lectures. To-day, they do not use a
text-book on the subject at the great law school of the University
of Michigan, and in all law schools it receives a degree of attention
small enough to surprise the layman. It is difficult, in New York,
at least, to find a lawyer of standing prepared, or even inclined,
to undertake a criminal case. Such facts indicate the state of the
criminal law,there is probably no equally important department
of human interest so neglected or in so primitive and irrational
a condition. The members of the community whom it most directly
concerns are the very basest,the criminals themselves. Those
next in interestthe victimshave very little interest
indeed; some of them because they have been killed, and the others
because they can seldom collect damages from the criminal, who is
nearly always impecunious; and therefore they have no personal interest
in developing the criminal law other than the old-fashioned one
of revenge, which is fast growing weaker and briefer. The only remaining
party interested (save a few studious people) is the community at
large, and that party is too busy with other things, even with the
law in its business relations, to feel any interest in the criminal
law but a spasmodic and very superficial one at the moment of some
exceptional crime. The criminal law is also at a special disadvantage
in being almost entirely statute law. Instead of being made by judges,
after thorough discussion by lawyers, it has been made by legislatures
composed of men of all sorts of pursuits, many of whom have no training
whatever for such work, and, like all men, generally have prejudices
strong in proportion as their training is weak. For all these reasons,
the criminal law is far behind the rest of the law, and behind civilization
and common sense. As an illustration: beside the theory that a man
must be punished for his intentionsa theory carried to the
extreme that if he is too insane to have intelligent intentions
he must not be punished at allstands the utterly opposite
theory that his punishment must depend upon the result of
his acts,if he intends murder, he is to be punished for murder
only in case the victim die. The man commits his act, is arrested,
and then the authorities wait, before trying him, for a set of physiological
processes in the victim with which the criminal has no more to do
than he has with the tides of Jupiter.
Since the foregoing paragraph was
written, the recent review of “Two Centuries’ Growth of American
Law,” in the Yale Bicentennial Series, is cited in the Nation
as showing that “progress in other departments of law has been far
greater” than in the criminal department.
No wonder that under such conditions
the question of the treatment of anarchists has had little more
systematic attention than occasionally hanging one who kills somebody,
or coming as near to it as the local law allows. And what little
attention it has had has generally been (with the exception of some
unenforced laws excluding anarchists) as stupid as the criminal
law in general, in finding nothing more educative than the old-fashioned
pains and penalties.
The main question of what to do about
anarchism is made up of three subsidiary questions,how to
treat the crime, how to treat the man whose opinions lead to the
crime, and how to treat the man in danger of forming such opinions.
On the first point, little can now
be said that can have any immediate effect. In spite of all that
can be said, popular vengeance is going to dispose of the red-handed
anarchist as it disposed of Guiteau and Czolgosz. No less an authority
than the late Dr. Beard told me that Guiteau was plainly insane;
but there were enough other experts to call him sane, as they called
Czolgosz, and he was killed. Czolgosz was found guilty of murder,
despite the judge charging: “If the defendant knew he was doing
wrong at the time, the defendant was guilty of murder.” So far from
knowing he was doing wrong, he believed he was doing righta
right for which he was ready to sacrifice his life, and from which
he, in his grave, could gain no good. Nobody doubts this. But there
is more. The Associated Press report says that after the charge
Lawyer Titus also asked the Court
to charge the jury “that if they were satisfied from the evidence
that at the time of the committal of the assault the defendant
was laboring under such a defect of reason as not to know the
quality of the act, or that it was wrong, he was not responsible,
and the jury must acquit.”
“I so charge,” answered the judge.
[192][193]
Yet the jury brought him in guilty, thereby asserting that a man
supposing such an act could be of service to the world, was not
“laboring under such a defect of reason as not to know the quality
of the act.”
But after Czolgosz was dead, the physicians
were unable to find anything abnormal in his brain; and therefore
he was not crazy, and it was all right to kill him. Note the reasoning
of our law: he had a good brain, and therefore should have been
killed; had he had a bad brain, he should have been saved. But the
statement that he had a good brain assumes that the physicians could
find all there was in the braineven the physical signs of
the insane notion that he could do some good by killing the President,
not to speak of the other physical signs of the other insane illusion
that the amiable President was, as the assassin said in his last
moments, the enemy of the poor people. Now, they could find no such
thing, though it was surely there. But they did not knownobody
knowshow to look for it. We know precious little more of the
topography of the brain than we do of the topography of Mars. We
do know gross outlines, and so sometimes we can tell when a brain
is grossly wrong. But then it is no news: for we knew it before
seeing the brain at all. We know regarding Czolgosz’s brain, or
at least have reason to believe, that somewhere in it were tangles
corresponding to the tangles of bad ideas that led him to commit
the bad act; but where the tangles were, or what they looked like,
or whether our microscopes could show them, we have not the slightest
shadow of a suspicion. And yet the whole country is satisfied with
the “moral responsibility,” whatever that may mean, of Czolgosz,
simply on the strength of what we do not know about his brain.
Now, can anything be more absurd than
the whole reasoning?
So new and complex are the relations
of these problems to anarchy, that even the wisest are inconsistent
before them. Senator McComas proposes to kill anarchists, while
he attributes to them “abnormal minds,” though this would not be
inconsistent if he were an advocate of euthanasia for the abnormal.
Possibly we can get a little light
on the causes of the absurdities and inconsistencies which hedge
the subject, and on how they may be avoided.
Before the discovery of the law of
evolution, with its implication of slow but constant gradations
in Nature, more importance was attached than now to rigid lines
of classification, though the lines themselves were often mere spider-threads
of abstraction. Nowhere does this attitude of mind survive more
vigorously than in the antiquated criminal law, and nowhere in that
mass of fossil ideas more than in those regarding responsibility
and insanity. A line is fixed somewherewhere, a half-dozen
experts on each side will disagree with the other side, and among
themselves; but on one side of that line, such as it is, people
are called sane, and on the other side insane. Meanwhile, all the
common-sense world knows that insanity ranges from gentle passions
for broad margins in unread books, or for superfluous lace handkerchiefs
or silk stockings, all the way to homicidal mania. Few people of
the world, the social or the scientific, are unaware that there
are forms of insanity unsuspected by anybody outside of the patients’
homes but their physicians. Everybody knows that anarchical assassinations
are frequently committed by the mildest of men, who are ready to
lay down their lives for humanity. If such a deed as the assassination
of McKinley, or King Umberto, or the Empress of Austria, or Carnot,
for the alleged reasons, is not proof positive of insanity, it is
high time the law’s definitions of insanity were revised. All the
world knows, even when it is hot for retribution, that in such cases
fine-spun psychical dissertations are cheap impertinences beside
the plain question: Did the man do this utterly irrational and destructive
thing? Why send for a doctor to tell you in long words whether a
medieval theologian would call the act a crime? If the world is
angry, the majority of the doctors are angry too, and the world
kills the man, and after it has had time to cool down, admits that
he was crazy, and that his very act proved it at the outset.
Considering that the whole philosophic
world has been wrangling as long as there has been a philosophic
world, over the question whether there is such a thing as moral
responsibility, what can we expect but absurdities when we take
twelve men out of the street, especially at a time of intense popular
feeling, and leave them to decide whether, in a difficult concrete
case, a man is “morally responsible?”
Now, what is the common-sense thing
to do in view of such facts,what would be done, as a matter
of course, if we were not under an antiquated code of criminal laws,
antiquated ethical subtleties, and antiquated impulses toward revenge?
Why, simply, instead of putting the insoluble question of the assassin’s
“moral responsibility” before the twelve men from the street, confine
the jury to the much simpler question, reasonably within their capacity:
“Did the man commit the act?” If they decide affirmatively, instead
of following the antiquated, stupid, and barbarous course of killing
him, try the [193][194] modern, intelligent,
and civilized course of curing him? There would be no more trials
protracted by quarrels of experts and by hypothetical questions
thirteen pages long, and virtually no more miscarriages of justice.
The criminal would at once be put where he could do no more harm,
and handed over to experts who would do the best they could for
a mind capable of his act. To cure him of his bad ideas is more
difficult, of coursecalls for more skill and patience and
human charity than was called for by the method of the people who
sent us our religion, of stoning him to death, or our method
of the halter or the electric shock. But isn’t it more sensible,
more Christian, despite the Jews who founded Christianity, than
to destroy a man as you would a mad dogespecially a man who,
the experts say, has a good brain?
Let us try to clear up, a little more,
some of the foggy notions regarding “punishment” amid which we have
grown up. One of the clear things in the fog is an idea of balanceof
justiceof that feature of the system of things which Spencer
has taught some of us to call equilibration, which was very early
expressed as “an eye for an eye and a tooth for a tooth,” and which,
for a long time later, made it the privilege, even the duty, of
a murdered man’s kin to take the murderer’s life or a money ransom
for it. But notwithstanding the persistence of these ideas, even
till to-day, as far back as nearly two thousand years ago a voice
of highest authority pronounced them antiquated then, and they all
simply mean revenge. A kindred antiquated notion is that the spectacle
of retributive punishment is a deterrent. Hence, a man no older
than I, can remember his father’s employees taking a day off to
go and see a murderer hanged. But cumulative experience says that
such brutifying spectacles did more to encourage criminal impulses
than to discourage them; while recent science talks about the mere
spectacle of punishment for a crime conveying some strange hypnotic
suggestion toward its commission. And our fresh experience regarding
the lynching of negroes seems to back up this mysterious scientific
dictum.
Senators Hoar and McComas both admit
the proved inadequacy of capital punishment for anarchistic murder,
yet Senator McComas proposes it.
Vengeful and deterrent punishment
having, then, lost its standing before Religion and Science, what
is there left to do about the criminal? To this mystery comes the
answer regarding all mysteries which has been distributed through
our part of the thinking world mainly by the cumulative labors of
Lyell, Darwin, Huxley, and Spencer, and later, and more specifically
regarding the criminal, by those of Lombroso, Férré, and Havelock
Ellis: “Study him.” Well, he is found to be (at all events, since
the days of the robber barons and bold buccaneers) a puny, stupid
being, on the borders, if not in the domain, of insanity. Nobody
who has seen much of criminal courts will deny this. Nearly all
the anarchist-assassins are of this low type in mind and body. When
the Kropotkins and Tolstoys become anarchists, they do no violence.
Most readers on these subjects have some idea of the marvels (from
an earlier point of view) that have been effected upon the morals
of criminals at Elmira and elsewhere, by mere physical treatment,good
food, cleanliness, massage, and regular living. Results also abound
that seem less marvelous only because they came from agencies more
directly moral. This experience is fast breaking down the old ideas
of punishment; and instead of regulating the term of the sentence
by the “degree” of crime, is tending to make it indeterminateto
be measured only by the time needed for a cure. Thus the idea of
killing a wrongdoer before trying to cure him is fast losing repute.
If after the experts have done their best for a reasonable time,
they become convinced that after all the man has not a good brain,
and is incorrigible, and never could become anything but a dangerous
member of society, then for the first time, if at all, the
question of killing him could reasonably come up. Much of the world’s
best thought is now occupied with the problem whether a defective
whose cure is hopeless, and whose life is a danger to others, should
be kept alive.
So far, then, our reasoning, such
as it is, seems to demonstrate that the only rational thing to do
with the anarchist-murderer is to hand him over to the mental experts,
and, as he is dangerous, confine him. The asylum is his only logical
destination.
Are there any other considerations
pointing the same way? Yes, the papers are full of one set. The
most efficacious way of making a saint is to begin by making a martyr.
As all reasonable people expected, the anarchists are now burning
incense before the portraits of Saint Czolgosz, and bringing up
their children to court similar sanctification. Killing, as we know,
tempts the poor creatures by distorted ideas of the hero’s death
and the martyr’s crown. Suppose that instead of making a martyr
of Czolgosz, you had simply declared him the lunatic he was, and
immured him in a place which inspires only pity and aversion: would
anybody be burning incense before his picture? Would anybody be
bringing up children to emulate him?
But be that as it may, it is plain
that for a good while to come, there is little to be gained by [194][195]
arguing for putting the anarchist-murderer in the asylum. Until
the world is controlled vastly more by reason than now, he is going
to be killedput to “the worst use,” as Carlyle said,made
a martyr of for his whole crazy constituency,instead of made
an object-lesson of the ridiculousness of their “cause.”
II.
Inasmuch, then, as for the red-handed
anarchist, killing it is to be, perhaps we may turn with more immediate
profit to the question of how to prevent the anarchist from becoming
red-handed, and we may as well include with it the question of how
to prevent people from becoming anarchists at all.
Of course, outside of the slow processes
of education and improved production and distribution of wealth,
these results must be effected by law, and the law must prescribe
that something shall be done. Also, of course, in the present state
of our ideas, that something must be in the nature of a punishment.
So far as we have reasoned, there would be only the threat of the
asylum in case of murder, and people would be slow to apply it before
murder.
The most intelligent writers seem
agreed that the principal cure must, after all, be educative. Yet
even those holding this view do not entirely deprecate some punitory
element in the treatment. For preaching anarchy, as for every other
crime, the present ideal is an educative punishment. The first principle
in seeking such a one has been announced by the leading teacher
of our age, in one of those utterances that prove his leadership,
to be that in decreeing “punishments” man should, as always, learn
from Nature, and make his penalties as nearly as possible like hers,direct
consequences of the acts themselves. Dyspepsia, katzenjammer,
much rheumatism and gout, all loss of vigor from overindulgence
or overwork, poverty from overspeculation or laziness, or even bad
judgment,all these and hosts of kindred evils are Nature’s
punishments. They follow directly from the acts themselves, they
are in a sense self-inflicted, they tend to teach the victims to
avoid the sins against Nature which cause them, and they are generally
accepted with a candid, submissive, and even stimulating “It’s my
own fault; I must try to do better next time.” Such “punishments”
are not only repressive, but educative, and consequently preventive.
Human treatment of the offender should follow them as closely as
possible, especially in the feature of making the undesirable result
as nearly as possible self-inflicted. In that element lies the “Serves
me right” which makes avoidance and repentance natural.
Of course we can seldom emulate Nature
with absolute success, but that is no reason why we should absolutely
disregard her example, as we do with the merely brutal repressive
punishments which are arbitrarily tacked on to the criminal’s acts,
without in any natural sense growing out of them. A parent whips
a child simply from being too ignorant or incompetent to impose
a more rational punishment. The state acts in the same way when
it kills, imprisons, or fines for offenses which have no more relation
to killing or to confinement or to money than they have to the motions
of the stars. The legislature of Georgia, the only State legislature
which has acted between the assassination of President McKinley
and the time of this writing, started in the old hammer-and-tongs
waydealing out only imprisonment and death, the former even
for preaching anarchy. President Roosevelt’s message, and the bills
of Senators Hoar and McComas, have done much better, though Senator
McComas likewise deals largely in imprisonment and death. But he
also, as do the other two, pays due respect to the two natural-consequence
punishmentsexclusion and exile, which have been widely discussed,
and are both generally advocated in the press. Both are absolutely
logical consequences of proclaiming anarchistic opinions. The law
can say, with irrefragable logic: You declare yourself at war with
organized society. Very well; you can’t expect organized society
either to move away and leave its territory to you, or to retain
in its midst a pronounced enemy whose like have proved themselves
dangerous the world over. If you don’t clear out, or if you ever
return, of course you leave us the only resource of putting you
out by methods that will make return impossible. Moreover, if you
go alive, we are not going to be put in the position of unloading
you on other organized societies, but shall send them means of identifying
you. If they are wise, they will also exclude you, and the only
place where you can actually stay is the only place where you can
logically stay,where there is no organized societythe
desert.
Senator Hoar, however, has carried
his logic to what may seem an extreme, in proposing deportation
of all anarchists to some island where they could work out their
own theories. Until all nations were united in such a course, and
probably even then, this would not do away with the necessity of
each nation guarding its own borders, while it would impose the
additional burden of guarding the island. A still graver objection
is that a community (to use the word provisionally: it could never
be a community) of [195][196] such
people would soon perish of starvation and mutual extermination.
You might almost as well empty an insane asylum on an island. Even
if their physical needs were supplied, if left free from the control
of saner people, they would soon destroy one another. One is tempted
to say that there would be a state of affairs beside which all previous
conceptions of Pandemonium would seem Arcadia. The spectacle might
be instructive, but it would be fatal to the participants, and too
horrible for the contemplation of the world. Euthanasia in the first
instance, or even the electric chair or the gallows, would be more
merciful, if less educative. Some writers say that an organized
society under the rule of the strongest would soon be evolved. But
that is too optimistic. Organized society presupposes a vast majority
of its members sane enough to recognize the necessity of organization,
and organization means control, if only by elected agents. “The
strongest,” even if elected by those whose principle (?) is against
election, would soon be assassinated.
But there has been proposed still
another course, not at all inconsistent with exclusion and exile,
more directly self-inflicted, perhaps even more obviously logical,
perhaps more educative, and leaving more room for a change of heart.
Yet it is very radical, and, so far as I know, novel. It has had
scarcely any discussion, and what little it has had has shown many
objections, though apparently no fatal ones. Yet further discussion
or trial may prove some of them fatal, or show other weaknesses
which are. Nevertheless, several competent persons have pronounced
it well worthy of serious consideration. I proposed it in the Forum
after Carnot’s assassination, and in the New York Evening Post
after McKinley’s. Later, I offered it in a Phi Beta Kappa lecture,
and it received some opposition and some hearty indorsement [sic].
The only other suggestion of it that I have seen was in the London
Times, but the writer expected effects somewhat different
from those I expect, and not so desirable.
Before stating it again here, I want
to say as distinctly as I can, that, although I have not read very
far into jurisprudence, especially criminal jurisprudence, I have
read far enough to destroy the simple faith prevalent among those
who have not read at all,that it is easy to make a law that
will cure any given evil. It has become a commonplace, but cannot
be said too often, that the most careful statutes often effect nothing,
and not seldom aggravate the ills at which they are aimed. The statute
books are as full of useless inventions as the Patent Office, and
any one suggesting a statute should have little more faith in it
than in other untried inventions.
The one I suggest is simply to take
the anarchist at his word. He says: “I want no government.” Say
to him: “All right. As long as you behave yourself and pay your
way, and do not endanger our health by bad sanitation, you sha’n’t
have any. The law shall not know you. So far as your person and
property go, government shall not exist. If anybody harms you or
robs you, there’s no government for you to appeal to. On the other
hand, so long as you claim no protection from us, we shall not look
to you for any: you shall be relieved from duty on jury and in the
militia.”
Now the very bold anarchist might
answer: “Very well. If you won’t tax me, I’ll take my chances.”
But this retort could not be pertinently made in one case in fifty:
for in more than that proportion of cases, he would have nothing
to tax. But if he should make the retort in a State where the poll
tax exists, the answer would be: “As long as you stay here, you
use our streets, with their lights and drainage, and though you
set aside the protection of our police and courts, you are inevitably
protected by our boards of health; and while we want to oblige you
as far as we can, ‘the law takes no account of trifles,’ and we
can’t separate the little cost of what protection you refuse, from
the cost of the facilities and protection you inevitably use.” Should
he have any property worth taking into accounta stock in trade,
for instanceGovernment could also answer: “Your goods have
to be bought by customers whom you could not get were it not for
our streets and lights, and police and laws, and your goods must
be carried to or by the customers by virtue of those same facilities;
the facilities cost us money, and we shall have to reimburse ourselves,
just as in the case of the facilities you inevitably enjoy while
you are here.” If the property were real estate, or stocks and bonds,
which must be ultimately based on real estate, the same argument
would hold: real estate is valueless without the government facilities
already indicated.
Possibly, however, the question would
not arise in practice; for if government protection were withdrawn
from the anarchist’s property, he might not be able to hold it until
the tax-gatherer should come around.
But there are graver objections to
the scheme. It may be said: “If you withdraw the protection of the
law, you are practically making the man an outlaw, and outlawry
is a medieval and obsolete penalty, and, with many other penalties,
has become obsolete largely on account of its cruelty and its tendency
to demoralize the community.” I answer: “But as a penalty of preaching
anarchy, outlawry has not been tried [196][197]
at all. It is a logical punishment for preaching anarchy, and it
certainly has never been a logical punishment of any
other crime, unless it be treason. But as a penalty of treason,
it was used, often corruptly and tyrannously, only to punish oppositionoften
justifiable oppositionto the government in power; never, probably,
has it been used against opposition to all government whatever.
Moreover, when used in darker days, it was attended with confiscation,
and it was given up largely because rulers used it to get possession
of their opponents’ property. But as logically applied by the impecunious
anarchist to himself, it would not be attended with such dangers
of corruption of government,there would be no personal or
dynastic considerations to interfere with absolutely colorless justice.”
It would, of course, be very stupid
for the judge to pass sentence by merely saying, in effect: “You
are convicted of uttering anarchistic sentiments, and therefore
you are sentenced to outlawry.” I doubt if he should “pass sentence”
at all. He should rather say, in effect: “As it has been proven
that you wish the destruction of all government, we go as far as
we can to meet your wishes, and it is decreed that hereafter, as
long as you pay your way and do not endanger us, government for
you shall not exist.” Then, of course, the judge could “improve
the occasion,” as the judge generally does.
When I have suggested this remedy,
I have often been told: “Why, you are advocating the very thing
that the country has been congratulating itself on having escaped,
and that McKinley’s noble and pathetic ‘Let no man harm him’ helped
save the country from.” Not at all; McKinley simply did not want
the man punished before trial and conviction, and the country justly
congratulates itself that he was not. Neither do I want the man
punished without trial and conviction.
I have also been met with the more
general objection: “You are advocating lawlessness.” Not at all;
I want the penalty made lawful.
“Then you want it made lawful to kill
a man or take his goods?” Where’s the novelty in that? It is already
lawful to do it in dozens of ways. You send better citizens through
greater jeopardy than such a law would impose on the anarchist,
to fight fire, to arrest the desperado, to brave pestilence, to
carry on war. You not only take the rich man’s money for schools
his children don’t use, and the money of people who have no children
to send, and the Quaker’s money for wars he loathes, but you take
the laborer’s and farmer’s and merchant’s money to pay protective
taxes, that the manufacturer may grow rich.
“Yes, but in all of those ways it
is done by duly appointed officers of the law.” Certainly, and in
this case I want the law to duly authorize everybody who is disposed
to do itto make all men officers of the law. Considering the
secrecy and pervasiveness of the evil in question, it cannot have
too many active enemies.
“But,” I have been asked, “do you
really want all the hoodlums, with perhaps a sprinkling of high-minded
enthusiasts, to begin robbing and stoning the anarchists?” No, I
don’t, and I haven’t the slightest idea that they would. There might
be a little disorder here and there, but I don’t believe that the
law would prove much else than a powerful object-lesson in logic;
and I do believe that that would effect more good than all harm
from pillage and killing. Yet, to be candid, the writer in the London
Times who proposed the same experiment, said that the anarchist
from whom government protection was withdrawn would be torn to pieces
before he left the court-house. I doubt if the same writer thinks
so now. If the anarchist were assaulted, the people doing it would
show an enthusiasm for government vastly greater than is generally
evinced by people in the habit of committing assaults, and the suggested
law would certainly have its educational side regarding such people.
But I suggest it mainly because of
its educational side regarding the anarchists, and not because I
think (for I don’t) that it would lead the rest of the community
to extirpate them by violence; I do think, though, that it would
tend powerfully to extirpate them by practically illustrating the
absurdity of their position, and by preventing recruits to so absurd
a position. People who lack or pervert the reasoning power too much
to learn through it, can often learn through experience. Suppose,
for instance, that Herr Johann Most, professor of anarchy in New
York, found facetious young gentlemen dropping into his beer saloon
and, after refreshing themselves, going off without paying, and
that then said Professor Most, on appealing to the police to arrest
said young men, were reminded that he had disclaimed connection
with the government, and of course could not have its assistance;
or suppose that, government failing him, on attempting to obtain
justice from an intruder, or to justifiably expel him, with his
own good right arm, he should get sadly the worst of it, and find
himself without redress; or suppose that before appealing to his
own strength, he should reflect that he was starting a quarrel which
his opponents could carry to the point of killing him without fear
of the law. Is it not probable that Professor Most’s pupils in anarchy,
seeing their teacher in such plights, would lose faith in his doctrines;
or is it [197][198] not even possible
that the professor himself, when so situated, might ultimately be
led, not only by lack of disciples, but by seeing new light, to
the abandonment of his chair?
Or take another case. There is more
than one amiable, cultivated, and wealthy man whose sympathies with
those less fortunate than himself are so much stronger than his
reasoning powers, that he is doing infinite harm to those he seeks
to help by preaching all sorts of quack remedies for their distresses,anarchy,
at least by implication, among them. Suppose such a gentleman wished
to divest himself of some of his real estate for the benefit of
those with whom he sympathizes so deeply, and that the lawyers would
not pass his title, because, of course, he could convey no more
rights in the land than he had himself, and he had forfeited the
aid of government in ejecting any one who might squat upon the property;
or suppose that he were to find that he could not get a notary to
attest his signature to a deed, or that if, through some inadvertence
of a notary, he were able to get his deed attested, he were to find
that his grantee could not get the deed recorded; or suppose that
his means of doing good were to be apparently increased by a legacy,
and he were to find the executors unable to pay it to him because
his receipt had no standing at the surrogate’s court; or suppose
he were to break his leg by stepping upon an insecure coal-hole
cover, and wish to sue for damages (perhaps that he might give them
to the poor), and were to find that the courts were not open to
him. The suppositions are legionoutside of any violence or
robbery that might be perpetrated upon him where, if government
were to take him at his word, and, so far as possible, dissolve
its connection with him, his education in the usefulness of government
would be powerfully promoted without any severe tax upon his unbalanced
reason. As most people, even the disorderly, know him to be a well-meaning
man (One who, even unintentionally, does so much evil cannot reasonably
be called a “good” man), the probability of his suffering damage
in person, or direct damage in property, from the withdrawal
of government protection, is not very great; but even if he did,
the circumstance would, it seems to me, be of no importance compared
with the good to be expected by placing him and others who would
abolish government, in their logical relations to it.
The treatment suggested, or any other,
should be visited with special care upon the preacher of anarchy
through the press, and the most competent juries should be impaneled
to pass upon the anarchistic subtleties of the yellow journals.
Senator McComas does not wish to touch anything but direct counseling
of violence, though he includes belonging to bodies at whose sessions
violence is counseled. But that is taking the disease only when
it has reached the acute stage. It is really disregarding the ounce
of prevention and using only the pound of cure. The egg of anarchy
is the repudiation of government, and that egg is sure to hatch
advocacy of the overthrow of government. It may be glibly objected
that this whole scheme attacks freedom of speech. But it is not
attacking freedom of speech to take a man at his word. Moreover,
doing so in the way suggested would abbreviate nobody’s freedom
to criticise the government in power: it is aimed only at opposition
to all government whatever. But even if it did attack free speech,
nobody is entitled to freedom of speech who does not grant it. Shortly
after Carnot’s assassination, the anarchists killed an editor in
Palermo for commenting unfavorably upon it; and a threatening letter
was sent to Dr. MacArthur, of New York, for his memorial sermon
on McKinley. Moreover, no government grants freedom of speech in
time of war, and the anarchists’ constant attitude toward the government
is one of war. The line is distinct enough on both counts.
But a tremendous difficulty does arise
here regarding the distinction between the anarchist who preaches
violence, and the anarchist who deprecates itthe anarchist
of the “deed” and the “philosophical” anarchistthe fierce
demagogue who would overthrow government by violence, and the gentle
dreamer who talks (to what purpose no one can tell) of the “far-off
divine event” of a people so just and kindly that all repressive
government will be superfluous. The idea of forbidding these pretty
vaporings is repugnant to freedom. Yet President Roosevelt speaks
strongly of the responsibility of “the foolish visionary who, for
whatever reason, . . . excites aimless discontent,”
and to myself, I confess, the inoffensive wambler with a touch of
genius appears more dangerous than the coarse agitator. I found
a larger proportion of impossible statements in Tolstoy’s recent
North American article than I remember finding anywhere else
in serious literature. Now, untruths are always dangerous, and people
of powerful imaginations are apt to utter them when they speak of
economics and politics, because usually they have not the character
of mind that really investigates these subjects, or even delights
in history. What they don’t know, they generally supply, as Tolstoy
does his admirable fiction, and Ruskin did his beautiful rhapsodies,
from their imaginations. Because their imaginations have done good
work in their own spheres, they use them with the same confidence
in spheres where imagination is dan- [198][199]
gerous. Ruskin raved over the seamy side of industrialism as if
there were no other side, until he periodically raved himself into
the asylum; Tolstoy’s final remedy for the differences of fortune,
is teaching, by example, that the gentleman must degenerate into
the peasant, and the scholar into the manual laborer. No realization
appears to have struck him that the peasant is evolving into the
gentleman, and the manual laborer into the scholar, and at an accelerating
rate; and that the true solution is to help the evolution in that
directionnot to encourage regression in the other.
Now, such amiable men as these, with
their wide and pseud-intellectual [sic] following, do more against
right reason than all the Emma Goldmans; and I will venture the
assertion that more moral support is drawn from their works by such
violent anarchists as know them, than from writings that have less
claim to moral elevation. But to limit the expression of such loftier
writers, and, much more, to “punish” them for it by withdrawing
government protection from them and their property, would certainly
be fraught with evil, whatever good might also follow; and therefore
it may be wiser, even if it should deny the education I have suggested
for a certain type of philanthropist, to stop at the line which
divides the dreamer of beatitudes from the preacher of war. To determine
where one merges into the other, we have the resource that has served
us, after a fashion, in other questions,that of leaving twelve
men to decide. And yet should the dreamer go so far as to advocate
the abolition of government now, it would probably do more
good than harm to take him at his word in some such way as I have
suggested. That could hardly be called a “punishment” in the old
offensive sense, and probably would bring no violence to the person
or property of any kindly and peaceable man.
It may further be objected to the
remedy I suggest, that, to be consistent, if the law withdraws its
protection from the anarchist, it must also withdraw its authority
over him. Certainly not, so far as keeping him in order; it cannot
prevent his defending himself if he sees fit; neither, then, can
it logically be prevented from defending itself if it sees fit;
and in its defense of itself is of course included the defense of
its constituent partsall law-abiding citizens. The preacher
of anarchy is not a law-abiding citizen, at least in spirit, and
will not be in fact as soon as we get rid of our false sentimentality
regarding free speech far enough to make preaching anarchy distinctly
against the law, as Georgia has already done, and as the President
and Senators Hoar and McComas now propose.
The most weighty objection I have
heard is, that turning the hoodlum loose upon the anarchist would
whet the hoodlum’s appetite for other prey. The answer must be found
in the answers to the further questions(1) Whether the threat
of doing so would not at once limit the opportunity, by shutting
the anarchist’s mouth and even smothering, with the logic of facts,
the illogical combustion in his brain; (2) whether, even if such
legislation did lead to occasional pillage, or even destruction,
of an anarchist, the evil would be greater than the good? This,
at best, can yet be but matter of opinion. In forming opinion, however,
it should be carefully remembered, let me repeat, that such violence
would not be lawlessness, but would be done for law’s sake, even
though on territory from which the protection of law is withdrawn.
Moreover, if the hoodlum should attack the anarchist, the rôle of
vindicator of law and government would perhaps do the hoodlum more
good than the violence of his vindication would do him harm. For
one, let me repeat again, I do not believe that any violence worth
considering would result, while I do believe that fear of it would
drive anarchists away and suppress incendiary talk, and that the
logic of the step would substitute much right thinking for wrong
thinking, at least among neophytes; and leveling reform at the young
is becoming recognized as the most hopeful direction to give it,
especially with anarchism, whose worst enthusiasts are young.
To outlawry and exclusion and exile
for the man who has only spoken, of course the objection
will be raised that the man has committed no crime, and that you
are punishing him in advance. The gentle and industrious Chinaman
has committed no crime: you exclude and exile him. President Roosevelt
went so for [sic] in his message as to say: “No man . .
. preaching anarchistic doctrines should be at large.”
Moreover, the objection illustrates the primitive ideas still prevailing
regarding “crime.” Of the many queer things that have been called
crimes, all the way from celebrating the mass to kissing your wife
on Sunday, there remains but a little residuum called crimes to-day,
and they all have the common feature of being acts considered detrimental
to the general good. Judged by this standardthe only one now
generally accepted by sound authoritiesthe preaching of anarchy
is a very serious crime, and legislation is rapidly recognizing
it as such. But even pick up the gauntlet as flung,are you
going to punish in advance? As reasonably ask: When you hear the
snake rattle, are you going to wait for him to strike?
Of course there are many more arguments
both [199][200] ways than I have given,
and many questions of detail, but if the main proposition is sound,
the details can be adjusted. The scheme is not advanced as a cure-all,
nor does it preclude the use of other remedies. At the worst, if
it were found productive of more harm than good, as so many laws
are, it could be repealed before it had done much damage.
To sum up, the suggestions advocated
here are:
I. Exclusion of immigrants of avowed
anarchistic sentiments. And I would exclude Kropotkin and Tolstoy
as much more carefully than I would exclude “Jerry the Red” (or
whatever the gentleman’s name may be) as their vaporings exceed
their fellow-prophet’s in subtlety and eloquence. Kropotkin’s lecture
tour here was making anarchy respectable in the season preceding
McKinley’s assassination. There is much nonsense talked about the
difficulty of exclusion. Of course it cannot be done perfectly,
any more than any other human function can be; but the Berthelot
system can make it worth doing as well as we can.
II. Taking the anarchist at his word,obliterating
his relation to the government so far as permitted by his unavoidable
use of government facilities and by his power of self-defense, which
power involves the reciprocal power of defense against him. To arrange
the details of this proceeding,the conditions of information,
indictment, testimony, court findings, etc.,is no easy task,
but it is far from an impossible one.
III. The exile of all persons treated
under II. who should continue recalcitrant after a reasonable time
for profiting by the educational facilities of that treatment.
IV. For the exiled anarchist returning
without permission, imprisonment for life.
V. For the anarchistic assassin (and
he is as much the assassin if he tries and fails, as if he succeeds),
the asylum.
It may be objected that I suggest
a heavier penalty for return after exile than I do for assassination.
That is a matter of taste; for one, I do not think so. But I do
not make the suggestions with any thought of “penalty”an idea
which I consider stupid and outworn. I merely seek, so far as I
can, the best sanctions for the suggested laws. The man returning
from exile might do so from the sanest of motives, under the most
natural and even commendable of temptations,piety for his
aged parents, or love for his wife or children or sweetheart: so
that for that act, taken independently of his anarchistic opinions,
the asylum might be the height of absurdity. The fact is that we
need something, and are on the way to have something, quite different
from either our present prisons or our present asylums. Elmira points
the way.
How much special espionage would be
needed to carry out this programme, or any other, can be determined
only after much discussion and experiment. Some valuable suggestions
touching it may be gathered from Mr. Pinkerton’s article in the
North American Review for November, 1901. Special difficulties
may arise in guarding against corruption and blackmail among the
officers, but why those difficulties need be materially greater
regarding anarchists than regarding gamblers and other objectionable
people is not apparent. The difficulties, whatever they may be,
would tend to diminish as fast as any programme might prove effective
in excluding, converting, and exiling anarchists, and preventing
accessions to their faith.
As already indicated, exclusion and
exile need to become general before they can have their full effect.
When banished from one nation, the anarchist should not be free
to make his home in another just as desirable. The suggestion in
President Roosevelt’s message that anarchism should be made “an
offense against the law of nations, like piracy and . .
. the slave trade,” is of radical importance. But to
appreciate reforms, popular sentiment generally takes a long time
after they have become clear to students, and this is especially
true when the reform, to be effective, must be in operation throughout
the civilized world; even international extradition, though long
generally approved, by no means yet covers everywhere all the crimes
it should. And as concerns the exclusion of anarchists, an enthusiasm
for freedom that can fairly be called an intoxication, has made
the freest nations in the world England, Switzerland, the
United Statesthe very vipers’ nests of anarchy. So to temper
that intoxication as to admit the stern logic by which alone, short
of the slow progress of education and morality, the growth of anarchy
can be checked, will probably take more than the fate of Carnot
and McKinley, or even the fact that such fate was met under the
régime of universal suffrage itself. The “educative effect”
that was expected from setting the ignorant to outvote the educated,
and those who can produce little to dispose of the property of those
who can produce much, whatever may be its showing in other relations,
has hardly been illustrated in the history of anarchism.
|